Next: The Well-designed Logical Robot
Up: Experimental Possibilities
Previous: AI
Psychological Experiments
Elizabeth Spelke [Spe94] describes a number of experiments
that she and others have done to discover and verify innate mental
abilities. The basic technique uses the fact that a baby will look
longer at something surprising than at something that seems familiar.
Here's one that was first done in 1973 [Bal73] and was repeated by
Spelke in 1993. There are experimental babies and control babies and
the experiment has two phases. In the first phase the control babies
are shown nothing. The experimental babies see an object go behind a
screen and shortly another object emerges on the other side of the
screen. The timing is such as would be appropriate if the first
object struck the second object and knocked it from behind the screen.
The babies are shown the phenomenon enough times to get bored with it
and stop paying attention.
In the second phase of the experiment the screen is removed. There
are two variants. In the first variant, the first object strikes the
second and knocks it onward. In the second variant the first object
stops short of the second, but the second object takes off as though
it had been struck. The control babies look at both variants for the
same amount of time. The experimental babies look longer at the
second variant.
The conclusion is that the experimental babies inferred that the first
object had struck the second when the event occurred behind the
screen. When the screen was removed, they were not surprised when the
expected event was shown to occur but were surprised and looked longer
when this expectation was not met.
The conclusion is that babies have innate expectations about dynamics,
i.e. are well-designed in that respect.
For details see [Spe94].
That was an actual experiment. Now consider some possible experiments.
Suppose we want to determine whether some abilities concerned with a
specific fact about how the world is organized is innate. We compare
a baby's ability to use this fact compared to its ability to learn a
fact about an environment constructed differently from our world but
logically no more complex.
Here are some possibilities. Since I am rather innocent of the
psychological literature some of them may already have been tried.
- three-dimensional objects
- I'm skeptical that a person's notion
of a physical object is fundamentally visual. Here's an informal
experiment I actually did. The subjects attempted to draw a
statuette in a paper bag. They could put their hands into the bag
and feel it as much as they wanted to. The quality of a subject's
drawing, except for surface colors, was similar to what that subject
would have produced looking at the object except in one case. The
object was a statuette of an owl, and the subject who misperceived
it as an angel produced an inferior drawing.
It would be worthwhile to use this and analogous techniques to
explore people's concepts of three-dimensional objects. I would
think that it is possible to investigate how babies perceive objects
they are only allowed to touch and then see. The baby could feel an
object in a paper bag and then see either the same object or a
different object. The hypothesis is that the subject would regard
seeing the same object as less surprising than seeing a different
object.
- anticipating the future
- To eat when hungry doesn't require
having in mind anything like a sentence. However, to know that one
will be hungry 4 hours from now may require it. Maybe this is where
humans and apes part company. Can an ape that is not hungry perform
a non-habitual action, e.g. putting a key by an empty food box, in
anticipation of being hungry later?
- unethical experiment
- A Lockean baby would do as well in
flatland as in our space. Imagine arranging that all a baby ever
sees is a plan of a two-dimensional room and all his actions move
around in the room. Maybe the experiment can be modified to be safe
and still be informative.
- continuity of motion
- The Lockean baby is brought up in an
environment in which motion is discrete. Imagine that the baby's
world is a Macintosh screen. Objects move without passing through
intermediate points. The baby moves an object by clicking on the
initial and final locations. The experiment is to determine how
well a baby will do in such a world. This one might be tried with
an animal.
- attention experiment
- If a baby is built to expect objects to
behave as solids, then it will be surprised when objects appear to
interpenetrate. It might pay longer attention to such a scene.
- inconsistencies
- Babies might or might not find Escher-type
drawings surprising.
- geographical representation
- Consider a maze with a glass top.
Does it help an animal find food if it can walk around on the top of
the maze before entering it? The top could have small holes that
the smell of the food could get through. One psychologist opined
that dogs would be helped and rats would not.
The experiment would test whether the animal can represent a scene
by something like an image.
- goal regression in animals
- An animal seeks a goal but discovers
that a precondition must be achieved first and undertakes to do it.
Then it discovers a precondition for the precondition, etc. Suppose
the animal has been trained to achieve B as a precondition for
achieving when A isn't already true. It has been trained to achieve
C as a precondition to achieving B when B isn't already true, etc.
We ask how far the animal can carry the regression. Say the animals
are dog which vary in intelligence, or at least vary in the ability
to learn the tasks that humans teach dogs. We ask is there an
innate limit for dogs or can smart dogs carry it farther than dumb
dogs.
Susan McCarthy informs me that when a performing animal is taught
a new trick, the trainer starts with the bow at the end and works
backwards. I don't know if this is related to goal regression.
- grammar via meaning
- Many of the discussions of a child learning
its native language seem to assume that the child learns grammar
solely by observing grammatical regularities in speech and having
its grammar corrected. Consider a child raised by an English
speaking nanny whose native language is Spanish and is addicted to
Mexican soap operas. It seems to me that this happens often enough
so that observations could be made. The child would then hear a lot
of idiomatic Spanish. It would be interesting to observe whether
the child would be able to tell grammatical from ungrammatical
Spanish sentence.
My conjecture is that grammar is learned as an auxiliary to
meaning and is not separately represented in the brain.
Next: The Well-designed Logical Robot
Up: Experimental Possibilities
Previous: AI
Contents
John McCarthy
2008-09-18